Any discussion about the faltering progress of international
climate policy usually ends up revolving around the role of climate ‘sceptics/deniers/contrarians’
– call them what you will – in sowing doubt about the science and therefore
obstructing political progress. I’m no climate denier, according to
conventional categorisations. If I’m a ‘sceptic’, then I’m sceptical about such
categorisations and the way they get bandied about with gay abandon in political
debate. So where do these categories, and the political objects and subjects
that populate them, come from? And do they make any sense?
This month’s issue of
Global Environmental Politics features a forum discussion on the phenomenon
of ‘climate denial’. Three authors – Gert Goeminne, Peter Jacques and Tim
Forsyth – propose quite distinct ways of accounting for denialism and for
assessing its political and epistemic implications.
For many commentators, high-profile denial of the scientific
reality of climate change is largely to blame for the impasse in international
climate policy. In the first paper, Goeminne conversely argues that the
phenomenon of climate denial is a symptom of a poorly-realised science-policy
relationship, rather than a cause of it. He imports the notion that antagonism
is an important part of the political from Mouffe and Ranciere to enable a
critique of hegemony and orthodoxy in environmental policy discourse. For such
thinkers, the relative resurgence of the far right (and occasionally the far left)
as a frustrated response to the economic crisis and the stifling consensual
environment of centrist, technocratic, managerialist politics is an example of the
return of antagonism and dissent. Following Erik Syngedouw’s recent arguments
in Theory, Culture and Society,
Goeminne suggests that a similar process may be at work in climate politics:
"Lost in the translation
from science to policy, the concernful work of composition that goes into the
construction of a matter of fact is obscured in consensual decision making,
leaving policy nothing but externalities to be managed in a technocratic way.”
Goeminne argues that science is
inherently political. By this he means more than just ‘science is situated’ or
‘science is uncertain and incomplete’. Rather, science is always-already
political, as the construction of matters-of-fact is inseparable from the
construction of matters-of-concern. This is not to say that scientific
statements have no meaning outside of political influences, but rather that
scientific facts have explanatory value in relation to the matters of concern
which give rise to them. This, following Mouffe and Ranciere’s antagonistic
politics, gives rise to questions of exclusion – of people, of non-humans, or
of alternative problem-framings:
“Understanding the task of
raising and addressing matters of concern as a work of composition ... is the
true political heritage of constructivism, conceiving politics as a struggle
for who and what is to be taken into account"
These political acts of
exclusion and discursive foreclosure (i.e. of depoliticization) generate the
conditions for a ‘return of the political’, often in the form of denial of the tenets
of climate science. A zero-sum game is enacted where it’s cap-and-trade or the
end of humanity. Science is politicized, politics is scientized. The only way
to express fundamental political dissent is therefore to couch it in scientific
arguments. It should therefore be no surprise that those who look to
alternative visions turn to those which feature “a straight denial of sound
scientific arguments”.
In ‘A general theory of climate
denial’, Peter Jacques locates the birth of the phenomenon not in the
straitjacket of global environmental politics but in an ontological framework
whereby the holders of certain (right wing) political ideologies perceive in
climate science an existential threat to Western models of free market economics
and development. Jacques criticises climate change deniers on epistemic and
ethical grounds, and draws striking (and highly provocative) parallels with the
forms of reasoning employed by ideologically-driven Holocaust deniers.
As pointed out by Forsyth in the
final piece, Jacques’ arguments contain a measure of contradiction. Jacques
acknowledges that erecting binary divisions between ‘believers’ and ‘deniers’
of climate change is both meaningless and unhelpful. He also recognises the
political character of science as described by Goeminne and critiques both
‘sides’ of the debate for attempting to reinforce untenable Enlightenment
ideals of science-as-authority and antidote-to-ideology. Jacques however slips
into binary mode in describing the ideological underpinnings of climate denial,
and implicitly suggests that these ideological trespasses into scientific territory
are at the root of the global climate policy impasse.
Tim Forsyth completes the triad
by joining with Goeminne to round on Jacques and his moralistic and ideological
definition of denialism. Forsyth urges us to follow the paths of the
radical-pluralist democrats like Mouffe rather than the mid-20th
century Critical Theorists like Habermas, the ghosts of whom stalk Jacques’
analysis of ideological reasoning. This means recognising diversity in
environmental risks and political norms, rather than clinging to notions of
absolute moral and scientific authority.
Forsyth also draws out some
geographic elements of the debate in arguing that the ‘exclusions’ which
Goeminne drew our attention to often include particular ways of understanding
the vulnerabilities of the world’s poor, while the neoliberal demand for growth
is not restricted to Western conservatives, as suggested by Jacques. The
political silences which Goeminne places at the root of denialism can therefore
also be seen as being generative of a discourse which excludes the kinds of
alternative problem framings which may be more relevant to environmental
politics in less industrialized countries. Both Goeminne and Forsyth cite
Agarwal and Narain’s 1991 statement on the injustice of universal greenhouse
gas metrics as an early example of the ‘kick-back’ against the orthodox
scientific/political framing of climate change. Rather than seeking ideological
or epistemic fault in the arguments of climate ‘believers’ and ‘deniers’, we
need to investigate how scientific and political norms have inflected each
other, and how this process may have moved the dominant discourse away from
some of the most pressing environmental and social problems of the day, with
the effect of disempowering and excluding certain political actors. Forsyth
thus leaves us with a lesson:
“Political analysis of
environmental science needs to consider how science and politics evolve
together, rather than identify one or the other as dysfunctional".
So where does this leave our
understanding of ‘climate denialism’, of the sort which we encounter daily on
blogs, websites, in newspapers and on our TV screens? What this exchange in GEP makes clear is that we cannot hope
to come to any understandings by conceiving of denialism in terms of a
‘deficit’, be that of epistemic competence or ethical integrity. Binaries
between denialists and believers have little conceptual worth, and neither do
binaries between science and ideology. Both sides of the debate frequently
portray themselves as defenders of scientific purity. Not only are such
positions untenable on the basis of observations of scientific practice and the
complex intertwining of ‘fact’ and ‘concern’; they serve to depoliticize a
deeply political field while excluding a whole suite of disparate objects and
subjects from debate. I agree with Goeminne and Forsyth that it is this which
is at the root of the kind of denialism which is so prevalent in the media and
in political debate. If we follow Jacques, then the solution is to root-out
malignant ideological positions and keep them away from the science. I’m with
the other two. If we want good environmental policy – and good science – then
we need to let the politics back in.
No comments:
Post a Comment